lunes, 14 de septiembre de 2020

Technology and Ethics: Overview CARL MITCHAM AND KATINKA WAELBERS

  

Technology and Ethics: Overview

CARL MITCHAM AND KATINKA WAELBERS

Since the mid-twentieth century, technological change has increasingly led to public debate. Concerns have been raised about the legitimacy of nuclear deterrence, dangers of environmental pollution, informed consent in medicine, privacy and computing, the safety and desirability of genetic engineering, intellectual techno-property rights, and nanotechnological risks. Given the large and increasing number of these moral discussions, one could anticipate that any companion to the philosophy of technology would include analyses of a diversity of ethical issues. The twenty-three chapters included here, covering topics from agricultural ethics to water technology, confirm such expectation. New technologies, now affecting and affected by all aspects of the human lifeworld, open up and have become manifold opportunities for philosophical negotiation and critical reflection.

In the regionalized field of technology and ethics discussions, there are two distinct types of interactions. One focuses on the ethics of technical professionals, that is, the specialized ethical codes appropriate to physicians, engineers, computer scientists and the like. Critical reflection on how technological change influences such codes of conduct has become an increasingly prominent aspect of the ethics of technical professionals. Another focuses on how best to extend ethics in general from its traditional focus on human–human interactions to human–technology–world interactions, with the world including both humans and the non-human environment. Questions have also been raised about the possibility of specifically ethical dimensions to some human– artifact interactions, especially with artifacts that may be so complex or sophisticated as to acquire apparently human-like properties of intelligence or emotional responsiveness. A third and quite different interaction between technology and ethics has attempted to turn ethics itself into a technology. In the present overview, however, emphasis will be placed on general discussions, without meaning to deny the legitimacy and importance of professional technical ethics, human–artifact interactions, or efforts to create a technology of ethics.

There are nevertheless dangers in general ethical reflections, not just with regard to technology but in any moral assessment that too quickly interprets challenges in positive or negative terms – or even neutral ones. Any judgment deserves to be preceded by careful description. As the playwright Harold Pinter wrote, “To supply an explicit moral tag to an evolving and compulsive dramatic image [is] facile, impertinent, and dishonest” (Pinter 1998: 18). What the Nobel Prize-winning British author maintained with respect to his own plays applies equally well to dramatic unfoldings in the techno-lifeworld. As the essays collected here show, we are in the midst not only of major plot developments in the human condition but also of what might be called a relighting of the very world stage on which we “all play our parts.” To give too quickly a determinate moral interpretation to this evolving and compulsive narrative would be facile, impertinent and dishonest. Indeed, philosophy must work to appreciate the enlightenments of history and the dramatic ideas being played out therein.

1.       From Cultural Criticism to Cultural Lag

Two influential and related general descriptions of the new stage lighting in which we perforce assume our roles emerged in the late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century social sciences. In Europe, a key figure in the development of what became known as the cultural criticism of modern technics was Georg Simmel. As has been argued by José Luis Garcia (2005), Simmel’s socio-philosophical study of money analyzed how what began as a simple enhancement of the means of exchange, through the monetizing of all exchanges, fundamentally altered socio-cultural life. This alteration, which Simmel identifies with the particular technical means known as money, applies even more to modern technics as a whole. The result of industrial production, mass consumerism, and “creative destruction” – to use Joseph Shumpeter’s illuminating descriptor for the unification of the technical inventive and commercial impulses – nevertheless tempers any unqualified Enlightenment, liberal or socialist belief in progress. Technological progress appears to bring not only the goods of increased wealth, reduced physical labor and extended lifespan but also the more problematic, unintended and not easily controlled consequences of alienation, bureaucratization and intensified decision-making – not to mention environmental pollution and transformation. For Simmel, Max Weber, Walter Benjamin, Romano Guardini, Günter Anders and others, the combination was creating a new type of cultural life that appears incommensurable with all that has been known up to this point in human history and within which people thus struggled for moral orientation.

A related argument took more programmatic form in cultural lag theory, which can be found adumbrated in Marxist analyses of the need for a proletarian revolution to take full advantage of the liberating potential created by capitalism, but was given distinctly American formulation by sociologist William Fielding Ogburn and philosopher John Dewey. According to Ogburn (1922), social orders are constituted by semi-independent elements that normally reinforce one another, as when religion and science present compatible cosmologies or governments fund teaching respect for existing political arrangements. Maladjustment occurs when a cultural ecology experiences differential change in its elements such that disharmonies are introduced. Leading examples are associated with new inventions in material culture that no longer mesh easily with existing socio-cultural habits, which then require periods of sometimes difficult adjustment. One example of such technologically generated cultural lag (from Ogburn 1964) was the period during which the social institutions and customs of road-building and -use had to adapt to the increasing speed of automotive travel. Establishment of the US Food and Drug Administration (FDA) in the early part of the twentieth century provides another case; prior to the industrial processing of food and mass marketing of drugs, no governmental agency was necessary to supplement traditions of experience and personal assessment to inform patterns of use.

From the perspective of Dewey, cultural lag presents special challenges for democratic theory, which can easily fail to appreciate how the unity of the modern state depends on new transportation and communications technologies. As Dewey observed, “Political and legal forms have only piecemeal and haltingly, with great lag, accommodated themselves to the industrial transformation” (1927: 114). “Cultural lag” praise for and reliance on forms of schooling and freedom of the press that have been weakened or captured by special interests “is everywhere in evidence” (Dewey 1939: 48). Numerous other cases in which science and technology have outstripped the social, political or intellectual capacities of a culture have been documented by anthropological studies such as those collected by Edward H. Spicer (1952) and H. Russell Bernard and Pertti J. Pelto (1987).

One of the most pressing mid-twentieth-century examples was the advent of nuclear weapons, which presented an enormous leap in scientific knowledge and technological power prior to any political adjustments that would ensure wise or prudent use. As Albert Einstein put it, “The unleashed power of the atom has changed everything save our modes of thinking,” thus calling for “a new type of thinking” – or, equally important, of acting. More generally, according to philosopher Hans Jonas, “Modern technology has introduced actions of such novel scale, objects, and consequences that the framework of former ethics can no longer contain them” (Jonas 1984: 6).

More positively, however, one can identify during the last half of the twentieth century in many Euro-American countries diverse pragmatic, institutional responses to techno-cultural imbalances. Recognition of the problem of environmental pollution, stimulated by publication of Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring (1962), led to establishment of the Club of Rome (1968) – which produced an influential series of studies on the limits to growth (see Meadows et al. 1972 for the initial volume, and Simon 1981 for a vigorous response) – and the US Environmental Protection Agency (1970). Additionally, in the United States, the Congressional Office of Technology Assessment was created (1972–95) to “assist Congress with complex and highly technical issues that increasingly affect our society”; in Europe similar initiatives were both adopted and maintained, with the Dutch Rathenau Institute (1986–present) being one good case in point. In the 1980s, challenges associated with advancing biomedical technologies led to the development of Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) and Institutional Biosafety Committees (IBCs) to ensure the free and informed consent of human experimentation participants as well as the health and safety of those working in or affected by this expanding technological sector. Since the 1970s, professional ethics in science and engineering has also focused reflection on such issues. Finally, the funding of Ethical, Legal and Social Implications (ELSI) research as part of the Human Genome Project, and the development in Europe of new democratizing practices such as citizen participation projects (Netherlands) and consensus conferences (Denmark), witnessed creative efforts to bridge gaps between technological change and socio-cultural patterns of action and ideas.

Broadly speaking, much of the applied ethics movement – from environmental and bioethics to engineering, computer and nanoethics – can be interpreted as a response at the level of intellectual culture to technological changes in material culture. Post1980, optimism about the ability of free markets to mediate adjustments can be read equally as an applied ethical–political theory about how to address cultural lag phenomena – an optimism that nevertheless deserves to be qualified, as much as the governmental response it seeks to replace, by the continuing emergence of problems associated with natural resource utilization, energy production and human-induced climate change.

Indeed, the sometimes ambiguous notion of cultural lag itself deserves to be qualified, in order to avoid assuming the primacy of technology. Is it not possible for intellectual culture to lead as well as follow material culture? Historical analyses of the rise of science and technology in Europe during the 1500s, such as Weber (1904) and Lynn White, Jr (1978) – as well as of the different trajectory of historical development in China (see, e.g., Needham 1954) – argue that ideas and ideals can be major influences on technological change. Thus it need not always be assumed that “lagging” aspects of culture must simply be altered in order to “catch up” with technology. When applied uncritically and interculturally, cultural lag theory can threaten to rationalize Eurocentric assumptions about “underdevelopment” and forced transfer of technology – in accord with the ideology of techo-economic development put forth by “point four” in President Harry Truman’s 1949 inaugural address (see Truman 1949 and Sachs 1992).

To repeat: It may be intuitive that various aspects of culture change at differential rates. But this need not imply that one aspect (whether behavioral or intellectual) simply lags behind another or has failed to adjust to an inevitable or non-problematic change in material culture, as if there were no choice other than running to remain upright on the treadmill of technology. Futurist Alvin Toffler, for instance, has argued for recognition of a phenomenon he terms “future shock” or “the shattering stress and disorientation that we induce in individuals by subjecting them to too much change in too short a time” (1970: 4). Building off Ogburn’s theory, Toffler suggests “there must be balance, not merely between rates of change in different sectors [of society], but between the pace of environmental change and the limited pace of human response” (1970: 5). Cultural lag theory can highlight the values of preserving proportionality, equilibrium and harmony (the right adjustment) among the parts of culture. For Toffler:

The only way to maintain any semblance of equilibrium . . . will be to meet invention with invention – to design new personal and social change-regulators. Thus we need neither blind acceptance nor blind resistance, but an array of creative strategies for shaping, deflecting, accelerating, or decelerating change selectively.

(1970: 331)

Achieving this selective change is no simple, technical issue of “catching up,” but selective decision-making about what constitutes the good life and the ideal society. It may also happen that altered elements become interactive in some new and equally balanced way that awaits recognition.

2.       Dramatic Tensions

On the stage lighted by technological change and its cultural concomitants there have emerged a number of not necessarily mutually exclusive dramatic ideas. Given their diversity, it is difficult to parse these ideas or to attach to them clear and distinct typological tags for tracking the emerging interactive narrative tensions. But consider enacting alternative responses to the following closely related questions: (a) To what extent do humans shape technological products or processes? (b) In what ways do technological products or processes shape human action and perception?

To the first question, responses run a gamut from beliefs that technologies are the free creations of humans to those emphasizing an inner logic or determination in technology. What might be called voluntarism argues that people freely create technological artifacts and see technological development as completely malleable. This, of course, tends to be a corollary to popular expressions of faith in creativity and innovation. By contrast, what is often called determinism sees technological development as following its own inner logic, with humans functioning as something like vehicles for its expression. Just as human beings are not free to think anything other than 2 + 2 = 4 (although they are, of course, free to speak otherwise), so they are not free to create a perpetual motion machine (however much they might aspire to do so). Such historical phenomena as repeated sequences of invention (stone ages always come before iron ages), multiple invention (the wheel) and simultaneous invention (the telephone, motion picture, and airplane were all independently invented at about the same time) suggest determinate patterns or autonomy to technological history.

To the second question, responses again spread out across a spectrum. What might be termed substantivism is the position that technological change strongly shapes or influences social, political or human affairs; all stone age cultures are basically the same, and, as technology globalizes, socio-cultural orders converge. By contrast, instrumentalism views artifacts as tools that can reflect and be used in many different ways by diversities of human lifeworlds; that Thomas Edison invented the telephone for business communications did not prohibit its subversive deployment for private talk. People shape their lives and cultures, then as individuals or groups incorporate and adapt technologies in whatever ways they choose – a perspective especially congenial with the research of Michel de Certeau (1980).

Combining these two spectra of ideas yields a two-axes matrix. One (the x-axis) would concern the extent to which humans shape technology; another (the y-axis) would focus on the extent to which technology shapes humans (Figure 64.1).

The better-known philosophical arguments have been in support of positions that fit most comfortably in quadrants II and III. Quadrant II involves a combined determinist interpretation of technological change and substantivist assessment of the influence of technology on society. The thought of Jacques Ellul, for instance, is typically interpreted as representative of this quadrant. Quadrant III, by contrast, involves some combination of a voluntarist interpretation of technological change and instrumentalist assessment of the influence of technology on society. Samuel Florman (1976), along with most engineers, not to mention most people, would place themselves in this quadrant.


This does not mean that quadrants I and IV are empty. For instance, David Collingridge (1980) could be interpreted as representing the quadrant that combines a voluntarist position concerning the creation of technology but a substantivist position with regard to its societal influence, once created. What has become known as the “Collingridge dilemma” states that early in its development a new technology is quite malleable or subject to a free shaping by human beings, although, once created, the technology takes on a momentum and influence that can be difficult to alter. The construction of the interstate highway system in the United States is one example: there was considerable freedom in its initial design, but since being put in place it has strongly influenced landscape, commercial activities, and patterns of travel. Another philosopher who holds a similar position is Jonas, with his “contention that with certain [free] developments of our powers the nature of human action has [necessarily] changed,” which “calls for a change in ethics as well” ( Jonas 1984: 1).

As for the combination of determinism and instrumentalism, the thought of thinkers as diverse as Karl Jaspers, Donella Meadows and colleagues, Julian Simon and Nick Bostrom might serve to illustrate an idea that may initially seem anomalous. Jaspers, Meadows, Simon and Bostrom all argue that technology is a means that humans can use in many different ways, yet one that nevertheless exhibits a developmental logic all its own. For Jaspers (1949), the course of history manifests a degree of independence, but in its different stages and especially with the arrival of modern science and technology, most explicitly with the atomic bomb ( Jaspers 1958), presents challenges to human freedom; in the present human beings must struggle to maintain Technik als Mittel, or technology as means. Meadows et al. (1972) and Simon (1981) both argue some degree of inevitability about techno-social progress, but divide radically on their interpretations of the human meaning and appropriate response. Bostrom (2005) argues for taking advantage of technological opportunities that have appeared for human self-transformation, to become transhumans.

Much ethics-relevant work in the interdisciplinary field of science, technology and society (STS) studies has nevertheless challenged the adequacy of one or more of the basic ideas constitutive of these quadrants. For instance, according to Ellul’s adumbration of STS scholarship, analysis of the character of modern technology reveals it to be distinguished by such key features as automatism and self-augmentation. Technological decision-making exhibits a pursuit of efficiency such that when engineers see one technology as more efficient than another – that is, as increasing output relative to input, in relation to some context – their choice is determined; they automatically choose the more efficient technology. Moreover, what Ellul terms the technical system re-enforces itself in a quasi-determinist manner. New technologies often and unintentionally have consequences that only seem to call for the development of ever newer technologies. Examples are easy to find: classic industrial manufacturing technology caused environmental pollution, which then stimulated the development of clean-up technologies, medical treatment technologies to deal with health problems that arise, and new, less-polluting technologies. The extent and density of technological artifice seems only to increase. From industrial production to medicine to warfare, human activity becomes ever more technological and thereby to engender a technological milieu that replaces previous natural and social milieux.

What appears persuasive from one perspective has nevertheless been contested by another. Arguing the social construction of technology, subsequent STS scholars have described in detail how one technology does not always replace another simply because it is more efficient; technological adoption depends fundamentally on some degree of acceptance or appreciation by humans, be they engineers, marketers or consumers. Indeed, different groups of people are always redefining what counts as efficiency. According to one highly influential study of the historical development of the bicycle, for instance, its technical evolution was more a result of competition between social groups for how the bicycle was to be defined than the pursuit of anything that could be called the most efficient two-wheeled means of transportation (Bijker 1995). From this perspective, increases in the technological character of the human lifeworld are more the result of social commitments to technology than of any domination by technology. In the marketplace, some technologies succeed while others fail – but the reason choices keep being made between one technology and another rather than between more or less technology is simply that technologies themselves taken as a whole are socially desired.


At the same time, complementary STS studies have argued that technological development is not always as free as it may appear in the quasi-voluntarist accounts of social constructivism. Technological developments depend not just on the laws of nature but also on what have been identified as “orgware” and “hardware” (Smits and Leyten 1991). Orgware is constituted by the organizational and institutional conditions that influence the development and application of an invention, from engineering standards and governmental regulations to suppliers of materials, distributors and customers. Hardware is constituted by the physical technologies already invented, regulated, distributed and purchased. In sum, although efficiency may not determine everything, neither are the makers and users of technology as free as they might sometimes think. Neither determinism nor voluntarism seems a fully adequate account of the complexities of the techno-lifeworld. Related arguments have been brought to bear to question the substantivismversus-instrumentalism divide. Substantivism appears to reify if not anthropomorphize technology. Instrumentalism is somewhat idealistic about the abilities of humans to understand what they are really making and doing. As an outgrowth of such contesting arguments, a number of theories have emerged that attempt to integrate or move beyond the particular insights of different quadrants.

3.       Dramatic Theory

Ideational tensions in the ethics of technology, just like observations tensions in empirical science, are synthesized in dramatic theories; and, even though the dramas themselves are more rich than any theoretical models meant to capture them, the theories provide pathways to enhanced dramatic appreciation. Two major theorists of technology and ethics tensions who have also challenged the oppositions between the four quadrants defined by substantivism, determinism, instrumentalism and voluntarism are Langdon Winner and Bruno Latour. Given their influence across a wide variety of discussions, it is worth considering each in modest detail.

Winner aims to go beyond descriptions of making and using in order to “examine critically the nature and significance of artificial aids to human activity” (Winner 1983: 749). There is more involved with technology than commonly recognized in the ways inventors, engineers, operators, repair technicians and the like make and maintain artifacts that others can pick up, use and then set aside. For Winner, both voluntarist and instrumentalist views constitute a “technological somnambulism” in which we sleepwalk through and fail to recognize the extent to which technologies reshape human activity and its meanings. Adapting a term from Ludwig Wittgenstein, Winner argues that automobiles, electric lights and computers have become “forms of life” – creating a culture that is scarcely thinkable without them. Taking the example of television, Winner notes how “none of those who worked to perfect the technology . . . in its early years and few of those who brought television sets into their homes ever intended the device to be employed as the universal babysitter.” Additionally, “if anyone in the 1930s had predicted people would eventually be watching seven hours of television each day, the forecast would have been laughed away as absurd” (Winner 1983: 257). But Winner is also critical of substantivism and determinism. Watching television is a choice, even when turning it off may not be as easy as instrumentalists customarily assert. Television is woven into the fabric of daily life with programs that are topics of office conversation and news sources and as the hearth around which household furniture is arranged. High-definition television was as much a creation of marketing, especially the marketing of sports programming, as of technical invention. Such observations invite consideration of what Carl Mitcham (2002), responding to arguments by Ivan Illich, has called technological asceticism.

With some nuance, Winner nevertheless observes how artifacts can “embody specific forms of power and authority” in at least two ways. In one, the invention, design or arrangement of a technology functions to enforce an often hidden political decision.

His example is bridges on a Long Island roadway that were made so low as to exclude the buses African Americans would most likely need to ride in order to access public beaches, thus effectively promoting segregation. (The particular example has been contested; but, even if some details are mistaken, the case well illustrates how artifacts can enforce political beliefs.) This case of what might be called a voluntary, instrumental substantivism is complemented by cases of what Winner calls “inherently political technologies” or technologies with a kind of existential influence. Assembly lines, for instance, demand that labor be broken down into simple, mind-numbing routines and require rigid workplace discipline; it is hard to imagine nuclear power not implicating authoritarian systems of control.

Winner’s examples argue how social arrangements that precede artifacts can be reified in their design and how technologies can have their own social-ordering effects. In both cases, artifacts can be said to have politics. To cite another easily appreciated example, most stairs and curbs are serious obstacles for less mobile people. As Winner puts it, such artifacts are political in the sense that they have “power and authority in human associations as well as the activities that take place within those arrangements” (Winner 1980: 290). Such an argument falls between yet combines determinism, voluntarism, instrumentalism and substantivism. Yet Winner has provided little in the way of response, other than to call for more consciousness and public participation in the design and use of technologies.

Latour’s development of actor network theory (ANT) can be read as another effort to provide a systematic framework for dealing with the kinds of issues to which Winner attends. Certainly it is the case that Latour strives to avoid “technological somnambulism” or deterministic pessimism – but in a way that, more dramatically than Winner, offers a new ontology of artifacts (or what he prefers to call an anthropology). Rather than seeking to steer a course between the Scylla and Charybdis of voluntarismdeterminism and substantivism-instrumentalism, Latour rejects two basic assumptions shared by all four opposing positions.

Actor-network analysis focuses on the continuous reassembling of the social. In Latour’s words, his concern is “how to resume the task of tracing associations” (Latour 2005: ch. 1). This concern devolves into two further questions, the first of which asks what is meant by associations. For Latour, technical and human associations cannot be distinguished from each other when it comes to their social or moral roles (Latour 2002). Both are agents, or what he prefers to term “actants,” in so far as they both exhibit figuration (shape) and traceability (traces of making a difference). When it comes to figuration and traceability, the actions of humans and artifacts are associations that are themselves associated. In other words, Latour fundamentally (dis)solves arguments between voluntarism versus determinism and instrumentalism versus substantivism by simply denying the modernist presupposition that one can distinguish subjects and objects, and then argue about which influences the other to what extent.

A second question focuses on how to trace the trail of associations, and the continuous change of the social. Effective activity (that is, agency, whether of humans or of artifacts) is always found in a shifting network. Agencies continuously form, change and break off associations. Understanding the social role of anything requires appreciating how arrangements shift and interact. The presumption that the two axes of the matrix are separable (voluntarism-determinism versus instrumentalism-substantivism) is not tenable. There is no substantial distinction between technological and societal development. The trail of a technology changing shape is inextricably intertwined with the trail of societal change; social and technological evolution cannot be distinguished because the two are not distinct. Latour even denies the distinction between “making” and “using.”

To summarize: Two arguments are central to ANT. First, a social role is granted to non-humans. The subject–object dichotomy is dissolved so that artifacts (and even natural objects) are conceived as agencies along with humans. Second, what is called the social never stabilizes, but is composed of associations that form, change, break off and re-form across time. The roles of different actants and the actants themselves are not fixed, but the network is a continuously co-evolving complexity.

4.       Theory and Description

In actant-network theory, what are constitutive features of actant agency? As already noted, these are figuration and traceability – which neither singly nor together constitute autonomy, one of the foundations of modernist moral theory. Technological artifacts, just like people, become agents when they exist in a form that makes a difference in the existences and actions of others. To elaborate, Latour adapts an analysis from Marilyn Akrich (1992), who has argued that the designers of technical artifacts place in them scripts indicating their functions or uses. Engineers, inventors and others inscribe worldviews and thereby define actant artifacts with specific competences, motives, aspirations, political prejudices and more. But technical artifacts function like film scripts: they provide frameworks for interactions with other actants; they do not fully determine such actions. Like a piece of music or a drama, they require the interpretation of performance. When a technology is used or performed, it is also possible for de-scription to take place, with new associations between humans and nonhumans leading to the emergence of new and often unpredictable agencies.

Artifacts and humans are described as co-shaping the social by means of multiple mediations: translation, composition, blackboxing and delegation. Mediation by translation occurs when a human actant, attempting to reach some end that it may lack – for instance, sufficient strength to achieve – utilizes another, often non-human, actant. But, when this detour toward an end takes place, the initial end of the original actant is changed by the involvement of the new actant, and both will reach their communal new goal instead of the first actant’s original goal. In mediation by composition, many actions and actants are already the result of a collection of human and non-human actants. For instance, in the manufacturing of an automobile, multiple artifacts such as chassis, wheels and axles, engines, sheet metal, and more are combined. The development of these technologies (which are all actants) depends on multiple negotiations between different humans and non-humans.

Mediation by blackboxing is a process that makes the joint production of actants opaque. The acts of a driver (normally a human actant) are the result of the automobile, road construction, traffic laws, the behavior of other automobile compositions, and more. That a driver was in a hurry is an inadequate explanation for some act of speeding.

Other users of the road can make speeding (im)possible, and so can the road and/or the car, all of which are typically placed in a mental black box, not to be considered. Being in a hurry is not even a necessary condition for speeding, since roads can be designed to keep traffic at a certain speed. In fact, the affordances designed into roads and many automobiles are scripts for speeding as defined by traffic laws. Finally, through the mediation of delegation, actants take on meanings in the sense that they produce special types of articulation that cross the boundaries between signs and things. Consider a comparison between a speed bump, a traffic sign and a police officer; the regulation of speed can be delegated from the policeman to a traffic sign or a speed bump.

Appreciating these four, interacting types of mediation introduces a shift in how action is perceived and described. The world comes to be seen as a constructed “concatenations of mediators” or as links of ever changing associations. Each point in the network represents an acting agent, like actors in a stage play or like puppets connected to their puppeteers. But there is no real author of the play. Nor is there a puppeteer who pulls the strings or a script that fully determines the play. The only scripts are the “programmes of action” of the different agencies (Latour 1994: 40). Action (or agency) “is distributed, variegated, multiple, dislocated and remains a puzzle for the analysts as well as for the actors” (Latour 2005: 60).

Summarizing again: In an actant network, the social role of technological artifacts is equivalent to that of humans. Relations between technologies and humans are comparable to relations between humans. Additionally, both humans and non-humans are agencies, but neither are autonomous agents. Actant agents act as they do as a result of associations with other agents, human and non-human. Human agents are not unique sources of action, but neither are non-human agents.

A brief but important aside: Although Latour is critical of modernism, he is not postmodernist. Postmodernism, on Latour’s reading, seeks to deconstruct the modernist social project and argues against the possibility of formulating a theory of the social or of the technical. Social agency is not possible; and society and nature, if they exist at all, cannot be objectively understood or studied. Contrary to such postmodernist claims, the a-modernity of ANT “retraces the social and society by subtle changes in connecting non-social resources” (Latour 2005: 36). Within ANT, agency continues to exist but with new and different meanings.

Two other philosophers whose work intersects in critical ways with this new theory of descriptions, especially in so far as the descriptions contribute to advancing the regionalized field of technology and ethics, are Don Ihde and Peter-Paul Verbeek. Ihde’s phenomenology of human-technology originated in primarily theoretical (instead of social theoretical) interests. Independent and in anticipation of Latour, Ihde thematized a set of human–technology–world mediations in which technology influenced not action but perceptions of world and self. In the two basic types of mediations, technology could be incorporated into the human or taken as part of the world. The former, symbolized by Ihde as “(human–technology)–world relations,” with one example being the use of telescopes, constitute embodiment relations; the latter, symbolized as “human–(technology–world) relations,” and illustrated by the thermometer, constitute hermeneutic relations. In embodiment mediations, a technology becomes a kind of extension of the body; in hermeneutic mediations, the technology has to be read or interpreted. Other mediations are constituted by alterity or otherness and background experiences of technology. But, more importantly, in embodiment and hermenutic mediations Ihde identifies an invariant amplification–reduction structure. The telescope amplifies perception of things at a distance while reducing the cone of vision; the thermometer amplifies accuracy of measurement while reducing sensory engagement with the world. All mediations, that is, are non-neutral in amplifying some experiences while reducing others.

Although Ihde does not develop the possibility, one could imagine an ethical argument for the pursuit of those technological amplifications in which reduction is itself minimized or exhibits a distinctly marginal character; in so far as amplification does not carry with it, human experience undergoes an unqualified enlargement. This would be analogous to efforts in risk–benefit analysis of technological actions to minimize risks while maximizing benefits. As a limit case, such amplifying technologies as eye glasses could become so integrated into body functioning that the (human–technology)–world relation would be better-represented as a technobody–world relation (eye glasses becoming contact lens “I-glasses”) with humans as cyborgs (Haraway 1985).

Both Latour and Ihde are on record as seeing their theories of mediations for actions and for perspectives, respectively, as at odds (see Latour 1991, Ihde and Selinger 2003). For Verbeek, however, Latour can be read as picking up where Ihde leaves off, as moving from perception to action. Whereas phenomenology in general attacks the subject–object dichotomy by explaining how reality arises through relations between humans and their environment, Ihde’s particular contribution to this tradition (which Ihde calls “post-phenomenology”) is to note how these relations are mediated (co-shaped) by technological artifacts. Ihde’s mediation of perception can be easily seen as complemented or extended by Latour’s analyses of mediation in social action. “Technology mediates our behavior and our perception, and thereby actively shapes subjectivity and objectivity: the way in which we are present in the world and the world is present to us” (Verbeek 2005: 203).

The mediating role of artifacts should not be understood as intermediate between humans and the world. Instead, mediation constitutes both subject and object. “Humans and the world they experience are the products of technological mediation, and not just the poles between which the mediation plays itself out” (Verbeek 2005: 130). At the same time, Ihde and Latour seek to overcome the subject–object gap in quite different ways: Ihde bridges the gap not by denying it but by showing how mutual engagements constitute subjects and objects. In support of Ihde, Verbeek then argues that “it is indeed meaningful to make a distinction between someone who experiences and something that is experienced, someone who acts and a world in which action takes place – regardless of how interwoven and mutually constituted they are” (Verbeek 2005: 166).

5.       Description Plus

This overview of technology and ethics began by drawing on an objection by Harold Pinter to those who would reduce dramas to moral didacticism, to suggest that to some extent moral judgments of technology ought also to be suspended in favor of careful observation. Descriptive ethics is a necessary prolegomenon to prescriptive ethics. However, in his Nobel Prize acceptance speech, Pinter (2005) makes a distinction between how, for him as a writer, morality must remain an open question, while for him as a citizen it cannot. In the play itself, “Sermonizing has to be avoided at all cost”; but in life, in contrast to art, sermonizing cannot be avoided. For Pinter, his point had to do with what he considered a responsibility to expose the lies and mendacity of United States foreign policy since the end of the Second World War. In like manner, analysts of the technology-ethics drama have often felt called to criticize modern technology on such grounds as its disruptions of traditional culture, alienation and the loss of human autonomy in mass society, destruction of a natural environment, multiple risks and dangers (material and political), or its dehumanizing (including post-humanizing) tendencies. In counterpoint, others have celebrated technology for its contributions to human welfare, freedom and progress.

Pinter has been lambasted for his moralistic sermonizing in terms that echo the castigation directed at many critics of technology for their alleged naïve romanticism of the past or idealistic and unrealistic proposals for such reforms as democratic participation in technical decision-making. (Interestingly enough, the celebrations of technology are much less commonly criticized for their naïve optimisms or unrealistic forecasts.) There nevertheless remains a philosophical obligation not only to move beyond the celebration of technological change with its attendant ideologies, but also to weave ethical analysis into normative discourse that can contribute to the abilities of citizens to appreciate benefits while exposing and delimiting or transforming wherever possible its self-regarding dominations or public and private harms. How to square moral philosophical analysis and reflection with normative assessment is as difficult as Pinter found it was to bridge the hiatus between art and politics.

The theories of ethical drama that have been associated here with Winner, Latour and their followers are cumulative products of a trajectory of dialogue on relations between technology and ethics that remain rich but largely descriptive in character. From Winner through Latour, challenges have been formulated to any narrative that would simply enact distinctions between voluntarism versus determinism or instrumentalism versus substantivism. The relation between humans and artifacts needs to be understood as a fluid network, in which a rigid distinction between the technological and the social disappears. But are there no down sides to such a sophisticated theory?

Winner himself has raised one when arguing the vacuousness of “opening the black box” of the social construction of technology in ways that can leave in place uncriticized existing power relations (Winner 1989). Another important objection is that Latour’s symmetry between humans and non-humans at once anthropomorphizes artifacts and objectifies humans (Collins and Yearley 1992). If humans are co-constituted by non-humans, then it becomes unclear to what extent humans can form their own moral character, the idea of normative ethics withers, and any argument that actants should behave one way rather loses force. Moral responsibility seems to disappear. How could someone be praised or blamed for an action or intention if these are constituted by a continuously shifting network of associations?

One body of work that seeks to negotiate a clearer path from description to prescription – that engages descriptive complexities in the technology-ethics drama while arguing the need for normative orientation – can be found in the work of Albert Borgmann. In Real American Ethics (2006), for instance, Borgmann agrees with Latour that the insistent mediations of artifice undermine any simple autonomy as a precondition of ethics and proposes with Winner a politics based in what he proposes to call “Churchill’s principle.” In 1943, when the Nazi-bombed House of Commons needed to be rebuilt, Winston Churchill, as prime minister, argued against an architecture of the new and in favor of reconstructing what had been, on the grounds that “We shape our buildings, and afterwards our buildings shape us.” As Borgmann also emphasizes, it is not the individual who shapes buildings; instead, “We do it together, after disagreements, discussions, compromises, and decisions” (Borgmann 2006: 5). Giving Churchill’s principle a more general articulation, Borgmann continues:

[T]he Industrial Revolution changed the stage of life from the ground up, and now the technological devices that surround us channel the typical ways we behave. Ethics has to become real as well as theoretical and practical. It has to become a making as well as a doing. Real means tangible; real ethics is taking responsibility for the tangible setting of life. Real also means relevant, and real ethics is grounding theoretical and practical ethics in contemporary culture and making them thrive again.

(Borgmann 2006: 11)

Recalling the matrix that provided orientation to the dramatic tensions of technology and ethics narratives, it is possible to imagine an analogous situating of ethics itself. On the x-axis would be the extent to which humans voluntarily adopt their ethical guidelines or have these determined for them, if not by nature then by reason or social institutions. On the y-axis would be stretched out an opposition between substantive and procedural moralities. As with the previous matrix, it is the second and third quadrants that would seem best-populated. Conservative fundamentalists argue determination by some substantially delimiting moral code, liberal constructivists for an inclusive proceduralism adopted in something like a social contract. Borgmann, however, criticizes liberal proceduralism as itself manifesting a semi-determinist influence of the thin way of life typical of the culture of high-tech consumerism and aspires instead for the free affirmation of a more substantive vision of the good.

We must, Borgmann argues, recognize the extent to which human freedom is a reality that leaves us able – and even calls us forth – to argue about what constitutes the good life within that material culture associated with advanced and ever advancing technology. The proceduralism of public participation is not enough. In a series of works that began with his philosophical study of Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life (1984), Borgmann has argued repeatedly for a substantive view of the good as composed of engagement with reality in both nature and artifice, and has sought to spell this out with both descriptive richness and normative depth. At the same time, Borgmann recognizes that philosophy engages the good by way of neither the apodeictic causal explanations of science nor the deictic witness of poetry; instead, in ethics, philosophy can only present the good in a paradeictic or paradigmatic form that at once throws into unifying relief an apparently chaotic world with an attractiveness that perhaps can open the mind and heart to greater things.

For Borgmann, this greater good is the conscious design of an artifice that recognizes its own limitations and promotes instead not simply more human freedom and mastery of experience but what he calls focal things and practices such as those exemplified by well-wrought material objects and the festive meal. Ethics, in Borgmann’s terms, is constituted by recognizing and responding to the claims of realities such as natural beauties and human virtues that, were they to be ignored, would diminish us as persons in our particularities as members of communities natural and social – that is, in landscape and country. In America, Borgmann finds real ethics dispersed in the new urbanism, environmentalist, and voluntary simplicity movements, and in his concept of focal reality he seeks thereby to concentrate and illuminate the multiple intuitions at their core. Even those who remain unpersuaded by Borgmann’s own paradigm for the realization of a more substantive ethics in the midst of American technological prowess, who criticize it perhaps as a romantic idealization of the past, may still be attracted to his approach as providing a paradigm of descriptive sensitivity woven together with an enriched and enriching normative seriousness.

domingo, 13 de septiembre de 2020

Ethics in Technological Culture: A Programmatic Proposal for a Pragmatist Approach

Ethics in Technological Culture: A Programmatic Proposal

for a Pragmatist Approach

Wageningen University

Maartje Schermer

Erasmus University Rotterdam

Michiel Korthals

Wageningen University

Tsjalling Swierstra

University of Twente

Neither traditional philosophy nor current applied ethics seem able to cope adequately with the highly dynamic character of our modern technological culture. This is because they have insufficient insight into the moral significance of technological artifacts and systems. Here, much can be learned from recent science and technology studies (STS). They have opened up the black box of technological developments and have revealed the intimate intertwinement of technology and society in minute detail. However, while applied ethics is characterized by a certain “technology blindness,” the most influential approaches within STS show a “normative deficit” and display an agnostic or even antagonistic attitude toward ethics. To repair the blind spots of both applied ethics and STS, the authors sketch the contours of a pragmatist approach. They will explore the tasks and tools of a pragmatist ethics and pay special attention to the exploration of future worlds disclosed and shaped by technology and the management of deep value conflicts inherent to a pluralist society.

Keywords: applied ethics; pragmatism; STS; philosophy of science and technology; normativity

Pragmatist ethics . . . is not only interested in the application of pregiven normative rules, but in the construction of new possibilities for moral action . . . [in] the creative character of the solution of moral problems.

—Joas (1993, 253)

In The Public and its Problems (1927), the pragmatist John Dewey described the rise of technological culture. Columbus may have discovered a new world in the geographical sense, but in reality, Dewey says, the new world was created only during the past century. “Steam and electricity have done more to alter the conditions under which men associate together than all the agencies which affected human relationships before our time” (Dewey 1954, 323). Dewey argues that these new technologies have contributed more to the establishment of modern democratic forms of government than the political theories of Locke and the utilitarians did. “The transition from family and dynastic government supported by the loyalties of tradition to popular government was the outcome primarily of technological discoveries and inventions working a change in the customs by which men had been bound together. It was not due to the doctrines of doctrinaires” (p. 326).

Dewey (1954) remarks further that the value of technological advances is seldom fairly assessed. These advances are generally held responsible for all the misery of modern existence, a widespread tendency that he dismisses as lazy thinking. “It is always convenient to have a devil as well as a savior to bear the responsibilities of humanity. In reality, the trouble springs rather from the ideas and absence of ideas in connection with which technological factors operate” (p. 323).

There seems to have been little change in this problematic situation since Dewey’s time. In a recent article, in which he posed himself the question of “how to live” in a technological culture, the Dutch philosopher Gerard de Vries concluded that the customary philosophical and ethical vocabulary is not properly equipped to formulate an appropriate answer to this question. This vocabulary is more of a hindrance than a help to a proper understanding of the technological culture (De Vries, 1999).

The problem we will be tackling in this article can be formulated in similar terms. On one hand, it is safe to say that the technological culture has a strongly dynamic character: old ways of life are continually being replaced by new ones, norms and values are continually being put up for discussion, and we regularly find ourselves confronted with new moral problems. On the other hand, however, neither philosophy nor ethics seem to possess a vocabulary that can accommodate this dynamic character adequately. In this article, we will first elaborate on the claim that the traditional ethical vocabulary falls short in view of the technological culture. Next, we will show that science and technology studies (STS) can make some contribution to ethical evalu ation of technological developments but that this contribution is currently limited due to the “normative deficit” of STS. We will then discuss how pragmatism can be useful in developing an ethical approach that is better equipped to deal with technology than current ethics. What we propose is not a complete alternative for other forms of applied ethics but rather a complement. To develop a new perspective on the moral and social problems and conflicts that are typical for a technological culture, we will thus bring together insights from applied ethics, STS, and pragmatist philosophy. Although, due to our programmatic intent, we will not be able to do full justice to each of these three disciplines; we hope to avoid sketching caricatures and erecting straw men.

The “Technology Blindness” of Ethics

Modern philosophy builds upon two traditions: an empirical one and a rational one. The foundation for the empirical tradition is formed by the work of Francis Bacon, in which a utopian program is launched, aimed at achieving social progress through scientific and technological means. The leading proponent of the rationalistic tradition was René Descartes. He regarded consciousness as the one and only unshakeable foundation upon which knowledge could systematically be constructed. The image of man that arises from modern philosophy is one of a completely autonomous subject who uses science and technology in a sovereign way to achieve his or her aims.

This humanistic and heroic self-image is still to a large extent characteristic of applied ethics. This discipline centers completely on people, their actions, and the regulation thereof. “Depending on the sort of ethical theory one supports, attention will be focused either on the presuppositions underlying actions or on the consequences of actions. In the former case, the question to be answered is whether the principle underlying the action satisfies ethical criteria, particularly whether it can be universalized. In the latter case, one asks whether the action contributes to the aggregated individual welfare” (De Vries 1999, 19).

As a result of this conceptual restriction, ethicists limit their search for the cement holding society together to the values, principles, norms, and rules by which people attune their actions to each other. However, society’s social and moral order is not only determined by symbolic constructions such as these, but just as much by material objects: “Fire, food, money, steam engines, dikes and polders, sewage pipes, viruses and computer systems have just as strong a binding effect as symbolic constructions, if not more so” (Harbers and Koenis 1999, 4).

As a result of its humanistic and anthropocentric self-image, applied ethics has been unable to move on from its technology blindness. If one were to look up the subject of “technology” in the most recent edition of Beauchamp and Childress’s famous handbook, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, one would search in vain. Nevertheless, it is obvious that technological advances in the very field of medicine and health care are an important source of moral problems and conflicts. Applied ethics seems to view technology mainly in instrumental terms; it can be used for good or for bad but does not form a subject of consideration in its own right. Apart from the view of technology as a neutral resource, technology is also often depicted as a threat, or as the polar opposite of good care. This negative view first appeared in Dutch discourse in a book by Jan Hendrik van den Berg titled Medische Macht en Medische Ethiek (Medical Power and Medical Ethics 1969), which played an important part in the rise of “principlism” in this country.1

To put it briefly, (medical) ethics is dominated by either a neutral or a negative vision of technology. In modern philosophy, both visions are now considered to be outdated. While classical philosophy of technology has given short shrift to the idea that technology is no more than an innocent resource, modern technology research has in turn raised doubts as to the utterly apocalyptic view classical philosophy of technology adopted to replace the instrumentalist vision.

Classical Philosophy of Technology

Classical philosophers of technology, among whom Martin Heidegger and Jaques Ellul were the most prominent, hold a substantive rather than an instrumentalist vision. According to this view, technology is anything but neutral. It opens as if it were a specific window on the world and determines to a large extent how we observe and assess reality. This is the case for every form of technology, from the most primitive to the most advanced. However, while technology was previously no more than one of many windows on reality, in “the atomic age,” it has infiltrated every part of our culture and established absolute domination. As a result, science, art, religion, politics, and philosophy have lost their own independent ability to unlock reality and create sense.

Heidegger argues that under the reign of modern technology, reality manifests itself as raw material for production and exploitation. The present environmental crisis illustrates where unbounded subjugation of nature to man’s quest for power leads. However, not only the environment but also people themselves are victims of the “anthropocentric violence” that seems inextricably bound up with the humanistic discourse of modernity. As the development of biotechnology has shown, man’s control over nature is not limited to the external environment but extends deep into the inner structure of the human being. Back in the 1930s, Heidegger had already predicted that the human being would be relegated to a mere “technicized animal,” once he became the main resource for technological control.

This conjures up an image with unmistakably apocalyptic characteristics. In the “age of his technological reproducibility,” the once all-powerful human being seems condemned to absolute insignificance. Technology has not brought about liberation but instead a new form of slavery, which casts all forms of slavery throughout history in the shade. This is also the theme of The Dialectic of the Enlightenment, by Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno. Far from being an innocent tool that can be used for both good and bad, technology seems to be emerging as an independent life form, which humans no longer control. Or to put it another way, not man but technology is in reality autonomous. It follows its own logic and knows only one course: that laid down imperatively by the drive toward maximum efficiency. This view, powerfully expounded by Ellul in particular and also known as “technological determinism,” has no place for the normative assessment and democratic control of technological innovation. Any attempt to offer resistance to these processes is doomed to failure from the start. Society can offer only one possible reaction to the unavoidable course of technological development: resignation, adjustment, and abstention.

In classical philosophy of technology, technology and culture form each other’s opposites and the idea of a technological culture could only be an oxymoron. Modern technology studies have abandoned this dualistic, in fact, absolutely Manichean way of thinking. In contrast, they now place the interplay of technology and culture at their center.

Modern Technology Studies

Modern technology studies have replaced the substantive vision of classical philosophy of technology with a pluralist one.2 They have made a resolute break with the gloomy view of technology as a Moloch, to the gluttony of which every expression of an authentic culture falls victim, and which leaves behind only a one-dimensional world. Modern technology studies split this monolithic concept of technology into a variety of specific technologies, each of which requires separate analysis. The focus thereby is less upon the finished product and more upon the processes and practices through which these products take shape. This explains the trend toward studying “science in action” on site in the laboratory.

Modern technology studies have opened up the “black box” of technological development and revealed the intimate intertwinement of technology and society. Both scientific facts and technological artifacts appear to be the outcome of negotiations, in which many diverse actors are involved. Technology does not therefore operate upon society as an external influence but actually forms an integral part of it. Furthermore, there is rarely one single path of development but rather a number of potentially viable alternatives, which fall by the wayside when they are unable to obtain sufficient social backing. Technological developments are not completely autonomous at all. They do not so much follow their own patterns but rather are a fairly random result of social interactions. Modern technology studies have abandoned the doctrine of technological determinism and for the most part replaced it with a constructivist approach. Constructivism does not view culture as unilaterally subject to technological imperatives, but argues that there is a coevolution of technology and society. To be able to introduce technological artifacts successfully into society, one must change certain aspects of society, while one can also say that the development and design of these artifacts takes place in a social field of influence, with many different players, each with diverse interests, aims, resources, and means of power.

It is of great importance for our argument that constructivism has vigorously exposed the normative significance of technological artifacts. According to the sociologist of technology Madeleine Akrich (1992), these artifacts carry a script or scenario within them. They require particular role patterns and lay down a specific “geography of responsibilities.”

The Scenario of the Pill

Modern contraceptive technology offers a good illustration of this idea of a normative scenario (see Oudshoorn 1995). The pill can be classed as a technology that largely delegates the responsibility for its use to the consumer. She or he may still be dependent on a doctor for access to this medication but is otherwise free to decide whether to keep taking it. One problem with this product is that it demands a great deal of self-discipline from the user. To remedy this, an implantable contraceptive was developed with a working life of up to five years and brought onto the market under the brand name “Norplant.” It consists of six small silicone rods, which are implanted under the skin of the upper arm and which gradually release a hormone. Norplant implies a different geography of responsibilities than the pill. Responsibility is partly delegated to the health care professionals; after all, a surgical procedure is involved, preceded by a gynecological examination, and followed by regular checkups. Responsibility is also partly delegated to the artifact itself.

“To compensate for the assumed lack of self-discipline on the part of the consumer, this new contraceptive was developed in such a way that it contains an inbuilt guarantee for continual use. The requirements formulated by researchers for the use of contraceptives were no longer delegated to the user but to the artifact. In this way, artifacts become ‘technical delegates’, to use Latour’s well-chosen term. They are designed to compensate for assumed ‘moral deficiencies’ on the part of the user and to bring discipline to the behavior of people” (Oudshoorn 1995, 281). Well-known examples of such “technical delegates” are door-springs, seat belts, speed limiters, and “sleeping policemen” (see also Latour 1993).

As with all new postwar contraceptives, the pill implies a gender-specific geography of responsibilities. The pill is meant for women, not men. This unequal division of responsibilities has prompted criticism from feminists. The female pill may have given women more autonomy over their own bodies, but on the other hand, they are also the ones exposed to all of the associated health risks. The development of a male pill, which is currently underway, would enable a more equal division of responsibilities and risks between men and women. Male interest groups have also made the case for a male pill. This is not so surprising, because the female pill not only makes women less dependent upon health care professionals, but it also gives them more power over family planning in comparison with men than was previously the case. “The script of the male pill is thus double-edged. While there is a more equal division of health risks and responsibilities between men and women, there is also a shift in who has authority over whether or not contraceptives are used” (Oudshoorn 1995, 286).

The example of the pill makes clear that technological artifacts provide people with certain social roles and power relationships, in accordance with their script or scenario. However, their influence extends still further. More indirectly than directly, they can bring about profound changes in our mentality and morals over a broad social front. To illustrate this, the pill can be taken as an example again.

Thanks to its high level of reliability, the pill created the possibility of separating sexuality from reproduction. This has had far-reaching consequences for sexual behavior and morals. The pill played a large role in the sexual revolution because it enabled people to experiment “unpunished” with their sexuality from an early age, with all of the consequences this has had for marriage.

The introduction of the pill was also accompanied by a shift in society’s perception of reproduction. Under the influence of the pill, a “birth regulation mentality” gradually developed. “This does not only mean that every child ought to be a wanted child, but also that people are planning their lives around the proviso that a child should only come—and then must also come—once the desired social and economic space has been created” (Ketting 2000, 285). This new mentality has had repercussions for the practice of abortion. There may well be much fewer unintended pregnancies now than before the pill was introduced, but the few that still occur are, as a result of this mentality, much less readily accepted than previously. If a pregnancy occurs before the set conditions have been met, then a request for an abortion will often follow. The annual number of abortions has therefore not actually decreased since the introduction of the pill. Whereas previously, the option of abortion came up for discussion only when a pregnancy was completely unwanted, it now comes up even if the pregnancy was just unplanned. “The interesting thing is that the simple fact of the pregnancy being unplanned, almost always renders that pregnancy completely unwanted too” (Ketting 2000, 285).

The example of the pill makes it clear that technological artifacts embody particular options and restrictions: they invite certain kinds of action or behavior and discourage other ones, and thus reinforce or alter existing role divisions and power structures. The normative ramifications of technological artifacts are rarely limited to the practice for which they are intended but often also filter through into associated or adjacent practices (in the case of the pill, into marriage and abortion). The significance of these insights for ethics has until now not been acknowledged sufficiently. Perhaps as a result of the anthropocentrism of traditional ethics, applied ethics has not yet opened up the black box of technological development. Though it does pay some attention to the moral problems invoked by the use of new technologies, it remains blind to the moral significance of the technology itself. This condemns applied ethics to be left running to catch up with the facts. More and more attention may be devoted to the everyday functioning of laboratories, hospital departments, and nursing homes, and there may be more awareness of the importance of negotiation and decision-making processes in the workplace, but this mostly remains limited to the actions of people, thereby ignoring the normative significance of technological artifacts.

As long as it clings to its “anthropocentric prejudice,” ethics will not be able to accommodate adequately the dynamic character of the present technological culture. Of further importance is that foundationalism, which has dominated ethics for a long time, is mainly aimed at underpinning moral rules and judgments on the basis of one or more universal starting points or principles. Consequently, little attention is paid to change of norms and morals over time, influenced by technological and other developments. The idea of change plays no significant role in ethical theory building. In the previously mentioned handbook by Beauchamp and Childress, this notion is also conspicuous by its absence. A search in the Philosophers Index or the Bioethicsline using the keyword moral change produces very few references. In as far as change is discussed at all in ethics, it is usually in an extremely limited way, either in terms of continuity or of the “slippery slope.” This can be illustrated by the debate surrounding biotechnology and cloning.

The Example of Biotechnology and Cloning

Supporters of biotechnology are often the first to argue that this technology is not actually as new as people think but rather just a small step in a long line of development. Biotechnology does not differ essentially from breeding technologies long accepted and applied on a large scale in livestock farming, agriculture, and horticulture. In the same way, objections to the reproductive cloning of humans are usually brushed aside with the argument that this is just “business as usual.” Ask whether we are not playing God, and therefore playing with fire, in practicing cloning, and you will receive the following answer from the American philosopher Ronald Dworkin: “But that is what we mortals have done ever since Prometheus, the patron saint of dangerous discoveries. We play with fire and accept the consequences, because the alternative is an irresponsible cowardice in the face of the unknown” (Dworkin 1999).

In the debate on cloning, the argument that there is nothing new under the sun recurs time and again. The argument that the transplantation of a relatively “old” cell nucleus could lead to a shortened life expectancy is met by the answer that we accepted such “irresponsible” risks when in vitro fertilization (IVF) was being developed. After all, no one knew back then how the first test-tube baby would get on. To counter the objection that the psychological well-being of the clone could be harmed by pressure to live up to the original, it can be argued that even children in “normal” family circumstances are continually confronted with a range of expectations. To counter the objection that we are coming to see children as products in which no defects of any kind are permitted, it could be argued that we already have such a view as a result of a range of existing technologies, such as prenatal genetic diagnostics or preimplantation diagnostics (see De Beaufort 1998).

By relying upon continuity arguments such as these, one denies that there is actually anything new involved. The new element is traced back to something that already exists, thereby rendering it harmless as it were. This is often an immunization strategy, with which people want to shield themselves from criticism and to prevent an extensive debate on the pros and cons of technological innovations.

The slippery slope argument is usually used by opponents of new developments. According to this argument, taking a first step on a particular road will inevitably and irreversibly lead to a whole series of steps, which in turn will lead ultimately into the moral abyss. This argument has also arisen regularly in the debate on cloning: “Straight from ‘Dolly from Scotland’ to ‘the Boys from Brazil’; no stopping in between” (De Beaufort 1998, 110). While the continuity argument trivializes the new element, the slippery slope argument demonizes it. This argument does not help move the debate further on either, which Inez de Beaufort argues is not unintentional. “The intention (of this argument) is actually to stop the debate. And often: to stop the practice” (De Beaufort 1998, 111).

The empirical version of the slippery slope argument is only plausible if one takes the view that technological developments have only one course, upon which society cannot exercise any influence at all once the first step has been taken. The logical version of the slippery slope argument is in fact a continuity argument.3 It goes as follows: once we regard a practice as morally acceptable, we will logically also have to accept other (undesirable) practices, as there is no essential difference between these practices. Here, by the way, the continuity argument shows itself to be a doubleedged sword, which can be used retroactively by opponents of a particular new technology to question the existing, already established, and accepted practice.

What all these arguments have in common is that they judge new developments from within the existing moral framework. The new is traced back to the old, or it is demonized, but this does not prompt any change in the moral vocabulary itself.

The Normative Deficit of STS

As a result of its technology blindness and foundationalist tendencies, ethics is barely able to cope with the change and renewal that is an everyday affair in a technological culture in a creative or innovative way. In this respect, ethics has much to learn from modern technology studies, in which the intimate intertwinement of technology and society is exposed in minute detail. As a result, modern technology studies seem to offer the necessary scope for the democratic control and normative assessment of technological developments. On the other hand, most constructivists have an agnostic or even antagonistic attitude toward ethics.

Within STS, two broad varieties of constructivism can be distinguished: moderate constructivism and radical constructivism (see Hagendijk 1996). Prime examples of moderate constructivism are the Strong Programme (SP) of Barnes and Bloor and the Empirical Programme of Relativism (EPOR) of Harry Collins. The insights of EPOR with respect to “interpretative flexibil ity” and “closure mechanisms” were transplanted from the sociology of science to the sociology of technology by Pinch and Bijker (1987) in particular. They developed an approach called the Social Construction of Technology (SCOT). Moderate forms of constructivism share the assumption that scientific and technological developments can be explained by social factors like dominant group interests or existing power structures. Radical constructivists profoundly challenge this assumption. The most important varieties of radical constructivism that nowadays are highly influential in the field of technology studies are the Actor-Network Theory (ANT), by Bruno Latour (1987) and Michel Callon (1987), and the reflexive approach to science (“reflexive ethnography”), by Steve Woolgar and Malcolm Ashmore (1988), among others.

Radical constructivists accuse moderate constructivists of substituting one form of determinism—technological determinism—with just another form—social determinism (e.g., Woolgar 1991). Instead of explaining technology on the basis of society and its structures, radical constructivists look at both technology and society as fabrications. They oppose the idea, forcefully put forward by Langdon Winner (1980), that artifacts have politics “built into” them. The discussion of Winner’s by-now-classic example of Robert Moses’s low bridges has made it clear that the politics of artifacts should not be interpreted as intrinsic and invariable features and that the kind of script that artifacts display depends on the specific context in which they are designed, developed, and used.4 Radical constructivists will subscribe to the first conclusion but not to the second one because they insist that we can not determine what the specific context looks like apart from the interpretations of relevant actors or “actants.” Here, we run up against what could be called the normative deficit of the constructivist approaches to science and technology.

It is certainly true that moderate constructivism is already lacking in normative respect,5 but with the turn from moderate to radical constructivism, normative reflexivity became nearly absent (see Radder 1992, 1998). Radical constructivists are committed to a “methodological agnosticism,” not only about what kinds of societal influences shape technology but also about what kinds of social, political, and moral impacts technology has (see Winner 1993). For the normative evaluation of emerging technologies, their favorite motto “follow the actors of science and technology without taking sides” means that we are totally dependent on the various interpretations of the different relevant groups involved, unable to choose between them or to come up with an interpretation from the “outside.” What counts as the capacity and effect of a technology is socially structured and is consequently contingent and open to renegotiation (Grint and Woolgar 1995, 298). But, as Radder (1992) rightly observed, such a “judgmental relativism” according to which any interpretation is as valid or as invalid as any other is impossible in practice. In view of this fact, two reactions can be observed. On one hand, some constructivists argue that symmetrical social analysis should favor the weaker side or “underdog” in scientific and technological controversies like women or lay people.6 But this partisanship is not only inconsistent with the methodological agnosticism that most constructivists endorse, but it is also quite arbitrary—a kind of a “crypto-normativism.”

On the other hand, especially within the actor-network approach, there is the opposite tendency or danger to analyze the process of network or system building exclusively from the winner’s point of view rather than from the loser’s point of view. According to Radder, the “winners-losers” terminology is suggested quite strongly by the military metaphors of the actor-network theory. According to Latour (1993), the constitution of norms and values should be described and analyzed in the same way as the emergence of facts and artifacts: not in terms of consciousness, cognitive power, method, fundamentals, and rationality, but in terms of allies and opponents, strategic negotiations, and tactical maneuvers. Regardless of how effective such metaphors, derived from war and power struggles, may be for questioning the standard view of science and technology, their use is difficult to reconcile with ethical deliberation, in which justified norms and values are sought in order to evaluate the development of technologies.

In his 1992 article, Radder argued that STS should overcome its fear of becoming explicitly normative. He concluded that one should “try to combine the achievements of the empirical approach—their more adequate views on the practice of science and technology—with normative insights concerning the problematic aspects of our technoscientific world” (p. 143).7 It is exactly this combination we have in mind with our proposal for a pragmatist approach to ethics in a technological culture.

The Pragmatist Alternative

So, while applied ethics has to a large extent remained stuck in its technology blindness and devotes insufficient attention to the normative significance and effects of technological artifacts and systems, modern technology studies are characterized by a certain hostility toward ethics.8 The impasse that has arisen from this can, we believe, be broken by a reevaluation of pragmatism. Pragmatism shares with constructivism its central insight in the coevolution of technology and society but differs from constructivism in that it gives serious consideration to the associated normative implications.

During the past few decades, pragmatism has made a remarkable comeback as a broad philosophical movement, not only in America but also much further afield. In Europe, even in the heyday of pragmatism, there was little enthusiasm for the works of “the classical quartet”: Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, John Dewey, and George Herbert Mead. The history of the continental reception of this American philosophy was a “history of misunderstanding” (Joas 1993). Due to its supposed utilitarianism and meliorism, this philosophy “from the land of the dollar” was dismissed on the eastern side of the Atlantic as superficial and opportunistic. But even in America itself, pragmatism lost much of its original appeal following the Great Depression. After the Second World War, it even seemed that pragmatism had had its day, and its place was taken by analytical philosophy.

However, in the 1960s already there was evidence of a turnaround in the appreciation of pragmatism. Remarkably enough, the first signs of this were observed in Germany, where, from 1963, Karl-Otto Apel and Jürgen Habermas gave lectures and wrote articles on Peirce and his pupil Charles Morris, and later on Mead too. Both expressly positioned themselves in the pragmatist tradition, describing their philosophy as “transcendental pragmatism” and “formal pragmatism,” respectively. Another important spur toward the reevaluation of pragmatism came from analytical philosophy itself, which began to show increasing signs of exhaustion in the 1960s and 1970s. The names of Wilfrid Sellars, W. V. Quine, and Hillary Putnam marked the main stages in the transition from a more analytical to a more pragmatist approach to philosophy. The final stage was reached with the work of Richard Rorty, the “Trojan horse of analytical philosophy,” who contributed as no other had to the current revival of pragmatism. Rorty has added Wittgenstein and Heidegger to the canon of pragmatism and, together with Dewey, declared them to be the greatest philosophers of the twentieth century. Furthermore, he has worked vigorously to lay bare certain “family resemblances” between pragmatism and postmodernism, as Derrida represents it in particular.

The Three Pragmatist “Antis”

Given this wide diversity of philosophers, it is clear that pragmatism must not be understood as a systematic theory in the usual sense but rather as a particular series of theses, “theses which can be and were argued very differently by different philosophers with different concerns” (Putnam 1994, 152). As Rorty continually emphasizes, these theses are in fact antitheses, that is to say, theses aimed against particular basic philosophical principles that form obstacles to a productive solution of problems and a satisfactory settlement of conflicts.

Antifoundationalism. Pragmatists reject every form of foundationalism and instead adhere to a distinct fallibilism. The “quest for certainty,” which philosophy has celebrated since Descartes, ought to be given up for good as illusory. All our convictions, without exception, are of a provisional nature and are in principle susceptible to repeal or review.

Antidualism. As well as foundationalism, pragmatists also reject essentialism. The dualism of essence and appearance is however only one of the many dualisms with which philosophical jargon has been punctuated since time immemorial. Other well-known examples are the dualism of theory and practice, of consciousness and external reality, of duty and inclination, and of fact and value. As we have already established, applied ethics and classical philosophy of technology also have a strongly dualistic character. They assume that there is a sharp dividing line between scientific facts and technological artifacts, on one hand, and moral norms and cultural values on the other. Traditional philosophy provides these distinctions with an ontological status and makes them a favored subject of metaphysical speculation. Pragmatists deny such an elevated status to these distinctions and give them only a functional significance, in accordance with their potential usefulness for problem solving. In other words, these distinctions do not precede research but are formed or construed only during the research itself, with a view to practice. The dividing lines between opposing concepts are not clear and fixed forever from the start but rather display a changing and fluid character.9

Antiskepticism. According to pragmatists, fallibilism should not be equated with skepticism. If absolute certainty is not achievable due to a lack of metaphysical guarantees, this does not mean that people are left at the mercy of universal doubt. According to Peirce, there is a world of difference between fallible knowledge and no knowledge at all. There is only more and less reliable knowledge. The Cartesian doctrine that philosophy must begin with universal doubt to finally obtain absolute certainty is not tenable.

We cannot begin with complete doubt. We must begin with all the prejudices which we actually have when we enter upon the study of philosophy. These prejudices are not to be dispelled by a maxim, for they are things which it does not occur to us can be questioned. Hence the initial skepticism will be a mere self-deception, and not real doubt. . . . A person may, it is true, in the course of his studies, find reason to doubt what he began by believing; but in that case he doubts because he has a positive reason for it, and not on account of the Cartesian maxim. Let us not pretend to doubt in philosophy what we do not doubt in our hearts. (in Stuhr 2000, 55)

Peirce distinguishes in this passage between real doubt and philosophical doubt, and argues for a symmetrical treatment of doubt and belief, with the understanding that the entertainment of either must be justified. One must have reasons to doubt, as well as to believe.10

Living and Working Together

These pragmatic antitheses are of importance for a pragmatist approach to ethics. The moral core intuitions of pragmatism revolve around the possibilities for living and working together. While consequentialists take collective happiness to be the moral touchstone and deontologists, the obliging character of moral norms, peaceful cohabitation and fruitful cooperation serve as the moral touchstone for pragmatism.11

This normative perspective sheds a specific light on the central (anti)theses of pragmatism. These can be seen as being directed against certain philosophical assumptions that often become, in practice, obstacles for fruitful cooperation. Because of their preoccupation with general and abstract truths, foundationalism and essentialism are often counterproductive—they distract attention from concrete problems and conflicts tied to particular times and places, which actually call for a measure of flexibility, hermeneutic tact, and context sensitivity. Dualism is counterproductive because it encourages “black-and-white” thinking, which brings conflicts to a head and leads debates to degenerate into unproductive boundary disputes or to get stuck in childish “does not”–“does too” exchanges. Skepticism, which cultivates philosophical doubt at the expense of real doubt, also forms an obstacle to a creative tackling of problems. Anyone who puts everything up for discussion will simply have no time left for the real problems of the moment.

Two “Progressive Problemshifts”

The moral point of reference of fruitful cooperation and peaceful cohabitation does not only shed light on the pragmatic antitheses and their internal relationship, but it also reinforces two progressive problemshifts that are characteristic for pragmatism. Because of its attention to the settlement of conflicts for the sake of further cooperation, pragmatism has always been interested as much in the process of (moral) inquiry as in its ready-made products (see Caspary 2000, 153). To promote the fairness and quality of the process of inquiry and deliberation, it is essential that all those concerned can have their say and that decisions are made on the basis of a careful consideration of all relevant conflicting moral claims and arguments.

A second shift to which the standard of fruitful cooperation and peaceful cohabitation gives rise is a shift in emphasis from the context of justification to the context of discovery (Caspary 2000, 161). Pragmatists attach as much importance to the justification of moral judgments as they do to heuristics, to the “art of invention.” Pragmatism emphasizes the importance of novel constructs and hypotheses with which emergent problems can be tackled, while in more traditional ethics the entire emphasis still lies upon justification of moral judgments.

The distinction between the context of justification and the context of discovery is related to what has been called the split personality of pragmatism, a term referring to the distinction between the rationalist and the romantic side of pragmatism (see Westbrook 1998). That pragmatism has shown both rationalist and romantic traits from the very outset was already noticed in 1911 by René Berthelot, who dedicated a critical study on the pragmatist movement (see Rorty 1998). Berthelot traced the rationalist roots of pragmatism to the influence of Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer, and the romantic roots back behind Ralph Waldo Emerson to Schelling and Hölderlin. The rationalist side of pragmatism is concerned with the cognitive capacity for argumentative problem solving and justification, while the romantic side is concerned with the creative capacity for the innovation and invention of vocabularies which provide new meanings and open new perspectives.

Tasks and Tools for Pragmatist Ethics

If we combine the distinction between rationalist and romantic aspects of pragmatism with the distinction between product-oriented and processoriented approaches, this results in the following matrix of tasks for a pragmatist ethics (see Table 1). Some of these tasks are well known to prevailing forms of applied ethics, but others constitute supplements that we believe are necessary to make ethics better geared to dealing with moral problems in a technological culture. We propose that depending upon the moral problem at hand, pragmatists will switch between these different tasks and their corresponding methods or tools.

Table 1. Tasks for a Pragmatist Ethics Product

Rationalist (“context of justification”)

(a) Traditional ethics Providing arguments and justifications for or against courses of action

(b) Discourse ethics Structuring and safeguarding fair public deliberation and decision making

Romantic (“context of discovery”)

(c) Dramatic rehearsal Criticizing and renewing vocabularies, exploring possible future worlds

(d) Conflict management Aiding an open confrontation of heterogeneous moral vocabularies and worldviews

The tasks in box (a) are the traditional tasks of applied ethics. Here, the role of the ethicist is that of the lawyer or the moral engineer. The main activities include providing, clarifying, and explicating various arguments, constructing moral arguments and justifying moral rules for (or against) specific courses of action. Common methods in applied ethics are principlism, casuistry, cost-benefit analysis, and so on.

The tasks in box (b) form the domain of the so-called discourse ethics, especially as it was developed by Apel (1988) and Habermas (1991). The goal of discourse ethics is the improvement of the rationality of public debate and decision making. Therefore, one should help to develop procedures and institutions that guarantee equal access to public deliberation and fair representation of all relevant arguments to ensure that moral decisions are based on the “force of the better argument” rather than on the forces of power, money, and the like. The methods of discourse ethics include stakeholder analysis (who has a stake in the matter in question and should consequently have a say in the debate?) and institutional analysis (to what extent is the institutional setting of the debate in line with the “ideal discourse situation,” as characterized in Habermas’s theory of communicative action?).

For more “common” and familiar types of problems for which the relevant ethical considerations are in principle known,12 the prevailing rationalist tools of applied ethics and discourse ethics usually suffice, while for new problems for which existing rules and routines are not adequate, it will be necessary to resort to the romantic side of pragmatism. In this final section, we will concentrate on this romantic side, since the rationalist side is already relatively well known. First, we will discuss some tasks and tools belonging to dramatic rehearsal and next some tasks and tools pertaining to conflict management.

Dramatic Rehearsal

The romantic side of pragmatism comes preeminently to the fore in what Dewey calls “dramatic rehearsal,” the imagining of a plurality of possible futures and the ways that lead to their realization. This involves thick descriptions of complex scenarios, of various competing possible lines of action and courses of conduct. According to Dewey, creative deliberation is dramatic in three senses: in its concern with character, which mirrors our dominant interest in the manifestation and interaction of personalities; in its concern for plot, for creative redescriptions and new narratives; and in its suspenseful and open-ended nature (see Caspary 2000, 113-14).

Dramatic rehearsal is similar to what Gustafson (1990) once termed the “prophetic discourse” in ethics.13 Gustafson distinguishes two varieties: the apocalyptic and the utopian. In addition to this distinction, another important distinction should be mentioned here: the distinction between future scenarios pertaining to technological culture as a whole and scenarios concerning separate technologies. The first type of future scenario takes on the character of cultural criticism and ideology critique pursued by authors such as Nietzsche and Foucault or by movements such as feminism or Marxism. Whole vocabularies, discourses, or broad technological developments can be criticized or put up for revision. Classical philosophy of technology in the tradition of Heidegger and Ellul that sketches a rather apocalyptic image of the future provides another example of this type.

For future scenarios concerning separate technologies, STS can provide useful tools—for example, the “material hermeneutics” of Don Ihde (1998). Material hermeneutics aims at the exploration of possible future worlds that are disclosed and shaped by new technologies and investigates the question whether our common moral vocabularies and our current institutional arrangements are still suitable or have to be revised or replaced in the light of these possible future worlds.

An example of material hermeneutics can be found in Schermer and Keulartz (2002). They take the case of IVF to explore the consequences and ramifications a new technique can have on society. IVF has increased the number of parties involved in the creation of a child. Not only commissioning parents, donors, and surrogates but also physicians, lab technicians, lawyers, institutions like sperm and embryo banks, infertility centers, laboratories, and surrogacy agencies are involved. A complex network is thus created, a network in which the embryo or child-to-be is the central knot. Schermer and Keulartz focus on the novel character of IVF and show the emergence of a new entity (“the embryo”), of a new medical practice (productive in stead of curative), and of new (family) relationships. They map the accompanying shifts in moral responsibilities and social roles and argue that these shifts have not always been adequately noticed and accounted for in bioethics.

Perhaps the greatest novelty of IVF was that it separated the embryo from the body of its mother. In doing so, it actually created a new distinct entity, the “early human embryo.” The embryo as a new subject has been discussed at length in bioethics. This was not the case, however, with respect to two other main issues that were raised by IVF.

The first issue concerns the division of biological motherhood. With IVF, it became possible to have one woman’s fertilized egg carried by a second woman. Thus biological motherhood (which could already be opposed to social motherhood) was broken up into genetic and gestational motherhood. It became possible for a child to have five parents: two genetic parents, two social or rearing parents, and a surrogate or gestational mother. Different combinations of gametes, wombs, and rearing parents render many different parenting arrangements. The possibilities for creating new family relationships, living arrangements, and forms of parenthood seem sheer endless. They signal the need to rethink the social, moral, and legal basis of family relationships and the meaning of concepts like family and kinship. However, these questions have received rather fragmented and one-sided attention in bioethics. Schermer and Keulartz (2002) claim that a pragmatist ethics would argue for an open and creative view on new family constructions and arrangements. A pragmatist ethics could argue for an understanding of the family in functional terms as suggested by Hickman (1999); it might explore a notion of “multiple parenthood”; or it might explore possibilities to understand “parenthood” in a more gradual way, with different degrees of involvement and responsibilities.

The second key question that is raised by IVF concerns the shift from private procreation to public reproduction. With IVF, Schermer and Keulartz (2002) notice, reproductive medicine literally became productive, for it created new life. The emergence of a new “practice” within medicine has gone largely uncommented, whereas it makes it necessary to create new concepts or a new vocabulary, to define new (social) roles and responsibilities, and to develop new rules guiding this practice. This new practice can be characterized by the fact that it treats people’s desires and not their diseases. It includes not only a number of reproductive techniques but also, for example, elective cosmetic surgery. Both reproductive medicine and cosmetic surgery are productive rather than curative and they create a different relationship between client and physician than the traditional one. This has been recognized insufficiently by traditional bioethics—a pragmatist ethics would emphasize the emergence of a new practice and explore possible arrangements for the new rules, relations, and responsibilities to go with that new practice.

Conflict Management

Assessment and evaluation of technological developments often bring to light deep-seated and fundamental value conflicts. Handling such value conflicts forms one of the main challenges for a pragmatist ethics because the problems that threaten cooperation and cohabitation are most pregnant and manifest here. Antifoundationalism and antiessentialism are important starting points here, since pragmatists will look for solutions in a more practical direction instead of looking for ultimate moral truths or foundations for the “only right answer” as traditional ethics tends to do. It is also important to recognize that the traditional liberal solution of making a split between the public and the private is more difficult to maintain where technological developments are concerned. Such developments often have a private as well as a public side that cannot be simply or clearly separated, as the case of IVF illustrated.

Like traditional ethics, discourse ethics is not always able to handle fundamental differences and disagreements in a satisfactory way.

Discourse ethics is mainly concerned with what Habermas has called “moral discourses.” Such discourses evolve around issues of justice, in which the question of “what is equally good for all” is central. In contrast, “ethical discourses” turn on the issue of the good life and on the question of “what is good for us” as members of a specific nation, members of a local community, inhabitants of a region, and so on. In ethical discourses, the attempt is made to reveal, through critical reflection, the deeper consonances in a common form of life that can bridge differences of opinion. Unlike a moral consensus such an ethical consensus is not (and cannot be) entirely rationally motivated. Participants in an ethical discussion can, after all, never work themselves free from the placeand time-bound perspective of the cultural form of life that is the subject of their deliberations. An ethical consensus can exist only within a single community. In modern pluralistic societies, however, discussions take place primarily between different communities, which often hold competing views of the good life. In that situation, an ethical consensus is impossible, and because ethical convictions differ from negotiable interests, a fair compromise is not suitable either; in ethical matters, one cannot bargain nor make concessions without compromising oneself and one’s integrity (Bohman 1996).

So the question becomes how to handle deep-seated value conflicts if the possibilities for consensus and compromise are eliminated. The answer we would suggest is that we should aspire to an “equal coexistence” of different ethical convictions.14 The ideal of equal coexistence requires a certain attitude of the conflicting parties. They have to appreciate the fact that they are competing for primacy within the same universe of discourse with others who cannot beforehand be branded as unreasonable. Such reflexive awareness rejects the naivety of dogmatic beliefs, recognizes its own fallibility, and leaves room for “reasonable dissensus.”

Pragmatists aim to develop different tools of “conflict management” to enhance mutual respect and to promote the ideal of equal coexistence. One method to make persistent conflicts manageable is breaking up dualisms and relativizing rigid dichotomies. This can be done through gradualization: thinking in terms of degrees instead of boundaries.15

One example of this is the debate between animal protectionists and nature conservationists about the moral problems associated with the introduction of large herbivores in newly developed nature areas in the Netherlands (Klaver et al. 2002; Keulartz et al. forthcoming). The herbivores released are basically domesticated species that are derived from hoofed animals that were once wild, such as cattle, horses, sheep, and goats. Konik horses and Heck oxen represent a special subcategory in this group, since they are meant to “function” as semiwild surrogates for such extinct species as the tarpan and the auroch. Most of them come from farms, zoos, or small parks, in short, from quite domesticated backgrounds; when introduced into relatively wild areas, they will be subject to a process of, what Klaver et al. call, “de-domestication,” that is, they have to learn to fend for themselves. The management policies of dedomestication, which entail minimizing supplementary feeding and veterinary assistance, have been most controversial. Most controversies revolve around the “domestication status” of the animals: should they be seen as (still) domesticated or as (already) wild? While the majority of the animal protectionists, farmers, and visitors view the released horses and cattle as domesticated animals to be cared for as individuals, most park rangers, herd managers, and ecologists prefer to treat them, ethologically and ethically, the same as wild animals in the areas at stake. Unfortunately, environmental philosophy is in no position to offer a way out of this stalemate, because within this branch of philosophy, there is an ongoing debate between individualistically oriented animal-welfare ethicists and holistically oriented ecoethicists that strongly reflects the polarized debate between animal protectionists and nature conservationists. As a result of this discord, people exhaust themselves in unproductive boundary disputes in which both sides claim an exclusive “moral jurisdiction” over large herbivores.

According to Klaver et al. (2002), this impasse can be broken if we replace the notion of a clear-cut borderline between nature and culture by the idea of a broad continuum, a hybrid middle ground, in which it is no longer a question of “either-or” but of “less or more.” Herbivores introduced in nature areas do not simply cross a distinct dividing line between culture and nature; they do not walk from domestication into the wild, that is, from a moral domain of individual care to one of concern for the ecological whole. They gradually move from a thoroughly cultural context to one that is increasingly natural.

To do justice to the gradual character of dedomestication, Klaver et al. (2002) introduce a new ethical notion with regard to the treatment of large herbivores in newly developed nature areas: the principle of “respect for potential wildness.” Emphasizing the potential aspect of wildness concedes a capacity for wildness, and at the same time, it acknowledges that dedomestication is a dynamic process with an uncertain and unpredictable outcome. In such a process, both animal welfare ethicists and ecoethicists will be indispensable. Klaver et al. launched this new ethical concept explicitly with the pragmatic intention to overcome the deadlock in the debate between advocates and opponents of the Dutch herbivores introduction program.

But often such a strategy of gradualization does not work well enough or at all, as is evident from the discussion over the status of the embryo in connection with abortion or medical experimentation. In this case, an attempt was made to break the impasse by redefining the embryo as a “potential per- son.” From the ensuing debate, it is clear how rigid thinking in terms of dichotomies is: while some say that we have no obligations to embryos because a potential person is not a real person, others think that we do have obligations, even to human eggs, because these are potential persons too. In this case, the concept of the potential person is once again seen as a question of “either-or” and not as one of “less or more.” If making the change from boundaries to degrees does not work sufficiently or at all, one will have to look for other ways to obtain an equal coexistence between rival vocabularies. A particularly promising way seems to be the so-called common-ground dialogue.16 Common-ground groups find it more constructive to leave core commitments off the table and to search for areas and issues where some kind of agreement is within reach. William Caspary (2000) describes as an exam- ple of this strategy the efforts to create a common-ground dialogue between pro-life and pro-choice representatives in the abortion debate. These efforts were motivated by dismay at the escalating incivility in clinic protests and public debates, and they also reflected a perceived stalemate in the courts and legislatures. Pro-life and pro-choice representatives met and discovered shared concerns about, for example, the expediency to reduce abortion by preventing unwanted pregnancies—teaching young people to resist peer pressure for early sexual activity proved to be acceptable to both sides.

Looking for common ground is in our opinion a promising way to combine two central tenets of pragmatism: the candid acknowledgment of the inevitable plurality of moral vocabularies on one hand and the commitment to work at finding solutions for the problems of human cooperation and cohabitation on the other.

Conclusion

In this programmatic article, we have intended to show that applied ethics has insufficient insight into the moral significance of technological artifacts and systems and that it therefore cannot cope adequately with the dynamic character of our technological culture. Analyses of this technological culture and of technological developments as are performed within STS are useful, but they fall short in normative respect. To repair the blind spots of both applied ethics and STS, we have sketched the contours of a pragmatist approach that does not represent a radical break with the current practice of ethics but rather is complementary in character. In the light of the central concern of pragmatism, cooperation and cohabitation, we have explored the tasks and tools of a pragmatist ethics. We have paid special attention to the exploration of future worlds disclosed and shaped by technology and the management of deep value conflicts inherent to a pluralist society. To develop an ethics that is well equipped for our technological culture, further theoretical analysis of the tasks we have suggested and practical experimentation with the corresponding tools are required.